THE
RISE OF HISTORICAL CRITICISM
So much for the rationalistic spirit of historical criticism,
as far as it appears explicitly in the works of this great and philosophic
writer; but for an adequate appreciation of his position we must also note
how conscious he was of the value of documentary evidence, of the use of inscriptions,
of the importance of the poets as throwing light on manners and customs as
well as on historical incidents. No writer of any age has more vividly recognised
the fact that history is a matter of evidence, and that it is as necessary
for the historian to state his authority as it is to produce one's witnesses
in a court of law.
While, however, we can discern in Herodotus the rise of an
historic sense, we must not blind ourselves to the large amount of instances
where he receives supernatural influences as part of the ordinary forces of
life. Compared to Thucydides, who succeeded him in the development of hisroty,
he appears almost like a mediaeval writer matched with a modern rationalist. For,
contemporary though they were, between these two authors there is an infinite
chasm of thought. The essential difference of their methods may be best
illustrated from those passages where they treat of the same subject. The
execution of the Spartan heralds, Nicolaos and Aneristos, during the
Peloponnesian War is regarded by Herodotus as one of the most supernatural
instances of the working of nemesis and the wrath of an outraged hero; while
the lengthened siege and ultimate fall of Troy was brought about by the
avenging hand of God desiring to manifest unto men the mighty penalities which
always follow upon mighty sins. But Thucydides either sees not, or desires not
to see, in either of these events the finger of Providence, or the punishment
of wicked doers. The death of the heralds is merely an Athenian retaliation for
similar outrages committed by the opposite side; the long agony of ten years'
siege is merely due to the want of good commissariat in the Greek army; while
the fall of the city is the result of a united military attack consequent on a
good supply of provisions.
Now, it is to be observed, that in this later passage as well
as elsewhere, Thucydides is in no sense of the word a sceptic as regards his
attitude towards the truth of these of these ancient legends.
Agamemnon and Atreus, Theseus and Eurystheus, even Minos, about
whom Herodotus has some doubts, are to him as real personages as Alcibiades or
Gylippus. The points in his historical criticism of the past are, first, his
rejection of all extra-natural interference, and, secondly, the attributing to
these ancient heroes the motives and modes of thought of his own day. The
present was to him the key to the explanation of the past, as it was to the
prediction of the future.
Now as regards his attitude towards the supernatural he is at
one with modern science. We too know that, just as the primeval coalbeds reveal
to us the traces of rain-drops and other atmospheric phenomena similar to those
of our own day, so, in estimating the history of the past, the introduction of
no force must be allowed whose workings we cannot observe among the phenomena
around us. To lay down canons of
ultra-historical credibility for the explanation of events which happen to have
preceded us by a few thousand years, is as thouroghly unscientific as it is to
intermingle preternatural in geological theories.
Whatever the canons of art may be, no difficulty in history is
so great as to warrant the introduction of a qeo;" ajpo; mhcanh'" (a 'deus ex
machina', or actor representing a god, brought on to the stage by a mechanical
device), in the sense of a violation of the laws of nature.
Upon the other point, however, Thucydides falls into an
anachronism. To refuse to allow the working of chivalrous and self-denying
motives among the knights of the Trojan crusade, because he saw none in the
faction-loving Athenian of his own day, is to show an entire ignorance of the
various characteristics of human nature developing under different
circumstances, and to deny to a primitive chieftain like Agamemnon that
authority founded on opinion, to which we give the name of divine right, isto
flal into an historical error quite as gross as attributing to Atreus the
courting of the populace with a view to the Mycenean throne.
TO BE CONTINUED