For, from the day when they left the chill table-hands of Tibet and
journeyed, a nomad people, to Ægean shores, the characteristic of their nature
has been the search for light, and the spirit of historical criticism is part
of that wonderful Aufklärung or illumination of the intellect which seems
to have burst on the Greek race like a great flood of light about the six
century B.C.
L’esprit d’un siècle ne naît pas et ne meurt pas à jour fixe (the spirit of an age is not born and does
not die on a definite day), and the first critic is perhaps as difficult to
discover as the first man. It is from democracy that the spirit of criticism
borrows its intolerance of dogmatic authority, from physical science the alluring
analogies of law and order, from philosophy the conception of an essential
unity underlying the complex manifestations of phenomena. It appears first
as rather a changed attitude of mind than as a principle of research, and
its earliest influences are to be found in the sacred writings.
For men begin to doubt in questions of religion
first, and then in matters of more secular interest; and as regards the nature
of the spirit of historical criticism itself in its ultimate development,
it is not merely confined to the empirical method of ascertaining whether
an event happened or no, but is concerned also with the investigation into
the causes of events, the general relations which phenomena of life hold to
one another, and in its ultimate development passes into the wider question
of the philosophy of history.
Now, while the workings of historical criticism in these two spheres of sacred and uninspired history are essentially manifestations of the same spirit, yet their methods are so different, the canons of evidence so entirely separate, and the motives in each case so unconnected, that it will be necessary for a clear estimation of the progress of Greek thought, that we should consider these two questions entirely apart from one another. I shall then in both cases take the succession of writers in their chronological order as representing the rational order – not that the succession of time is always the succession of ideas, or that dialectics moves ever in the straight line in which Hegel conceives its advance. In Greek thought, as elsewhere, there are periods of stagnation and apparent retrogression, yet their intellectual development, not merely in the question of historical criticism, but in their poetry and their philosophy, seems so essentially normal, so free from all disturbing external influences, so peculiarly rational, that in following in the footsteps of time we shall really be progressing in the order sanctioned by reason.
At an early period in their intellectual
development the Greeks reached that critical point in the history of every
civilized nation, when speculative invades the domain of revealed truth, when
the spiritual ideas of the people can no longer be satisfied by the lower,
material conceptions of their inspired writers, and when men find it impossible
to pour the new wine of free thought into the old bottles of a narrow and
a trammelling creed.
From their Aryan ancestors they had received the fatal legacy of a mythology
stained with immoral and monstrous stories which strove to hide the rational
order of nature in a chaos of miracles, and to mar by imputed wickedness the
perfection of God's nature - a very shirt of Nessos in which the Heracles
of rationalism barely escaped annihilation. Now while undoubtedly the speculation
of Thales, and the alluring analogies of law and order afforded by physical
science, were most important forces in encouraging the rise of the spirit
of scepticism, yet it was on its ethical side that the Greek mythology was
chiefly open to attack.
It is difficult to shake the popular belief in miracles, but no man will admit
sin and immorality as attributes of the Ideal he worships; so the first symptoms
of a new order of thought are shown in the passionate outcries of Xenophanes
and Heraclitos against the evil things said by Homer of the sons of God; and
in the story told of Pythagoras, how that he saw tortured in Hell the "two
founders of Greek theology", we can recognise the rise of the Aufklarung
a clearly as we see the Reformation foreshadowed in the Inferno of Dante.
Any honest belief, then, in the plain truth of these stories soon succumbed
before the destructive effects of the a priori ethical criticism of this school;
but the orthodox party, as is their custom, found immediately a convenient
shelter under the aegis of the doctrine of metaphors and concealed meanings.
To this allegorical school the tale of the fight around the walls of Troy
was a mystery, behind which, as behind a veil, were hidden certain moral and
physical truths. The contest between Athena and Ares was that eternal contest
between rational thought and the brute force of ignorance; the arrows which
rattled in the quiver of the "Far Darter" were no longer the instruments
of vengeance shot from the golden bow of the child of God, but the common
rays of the sun, which was itself nothing but a mere inert mass of burning
metal.